Matches in DBpedia 2014 for { <http://dbpedia.org/resource/Tonino_Griffero> ?p ?o. }
Showing items 1 to 75 of
75
with 100 items per page.
- Tonino_Griffero abstract "Tonino Griffero (Asti, 1958) is an Italian philosopher and currently Professor of Aesthetics at the University of Rome Tor Vergata. He studied at the University of Turin (where he graduated in Philosophy under Gianni Vattimo's guidance in 1982) with a work on E. D. Hirsch's hermeneutics. Later he received his Ph.D from the University of Bologna (1992) and conducted post-doctoral research in Heidelberg as Humboldt-Fellow (1998–1999). He has been a Researcher of philosophy at the University of Vercelli (1994–1999), then since 1999 an Associate Professor in Aesthetics at the University of Rome Tor Vergata. Since 2002 he is Full Professor of Aesthetics in the same University. He has been (since 2007) the founder and Director of Sensibilia-Colloquium on Perception and Experience. He is Director of a philosophical Journal ("Lebenswelt. Aesthetics and Philosophy of Experience"; http://riviste.unimi.it/index.php/Lebenswelt/index) and of the following editorial series: "Oltre lo sguardo. Itinerari di Filosofia" (Armando Editore, Rome), "Percezioni. Estetica & Fenomenologia" (Christian Marinotti, Milan), "Sensibilia" (Mimesis, Milan).1.HermeneuticsStarting from researches on history of hermeneutics, methodic hermeneutics, the problem of author’s intention, the canon of perfection of work, etc., the first work is on Emilio Betti(Interpretare. La teoria di Emilio Betti e il suo contesto, Rosemberg & Sellier, Turin 1988) that is not only author of a legal hermeneutics, but the leading exponent of methodic hermeneutics in the twentieth century. His great work (1955) concerns the conditions, the manner and the scope of understanding (in humanities) the inner world of another living subjectivity. Being in contrast with the trend to resolve the encounter with the texts in an ever new and arbitrary attribution of meaning, Betti claims a relative objectivity of meaning, attainable through the application of methods that are not tied to natural sciences.The second field of research are the hermeneutic investigations of Eduard Spranger (Spirito e forme di vita. La filosofia della cultura di Eduard Spranger, Franco Angeli, Milan 1990) a “classic” author of pedagogy and psychology as Geisteswissenschaften. His philosophical biography shows a thinker who keeps his distance from both positivism and the irrationalistic outcome of existentialism and radical historicism. Through several key problems (philosophy of life, personal values and stylization of forms of life, cultural, ethical and religious primacy of conscience), the neo-humanism of Spranger seeks an a-priori normative spiritual cosmos, that, although it is reflected in historically changing perspectives, ensures the structural homology between the individual and comprehensive structures of social world.2.Schelling and aesthetics of German idealismThe first work in this new field of research focuses the “first” Schelling (Senso e immagine. Simbolo e mito nel primo Schelling Guerini, Milan 1994, that seeks a kind of “golden age” in which the natural and spiritual world are and tell their meaning without breaks or allegorical references, through a narrative style, that is not yet forced to choose between sense and image, and so is really "symbolic" (as identity of finite and infinite, image and meaning, being and meaning), but also through a philosophy of identity whose meaning is an aesthetic and political utopia.The second work Cosmo Arte Natura. Itinerari schellinghiani CUEM, Milan 1995, focuses the ambivalent face, philosophical-esoteric and aesthetic-exoteric, which governs the first real-idealism of Schelling (1792–1809). On the one hand, he reinterprets the concept of Fichte's philosophy as a history of self-consciousness, the inescapable role of the unconscious and the access to the absolute by intuition, and on the second, he proposes an exemplarism based on an ontological and aesthetic universe, fights again the “bad infinity” of the Modern as well as the related philosophical split between scientific and folk consciousnessThe general aestheticization of individual and social that characterizes the "postmodern condition" seems to confer a renewed topicality to aesthetics of German idealism. The third book L'estetica di Schelling Laterza, Rome-Bari 1996) reconstructs the entire aesthetics of Schelling showing her evolution and transformation from the juvenile system of identity to the more mature and disenchanted system.3.Transitive imaginationThe belief in the power of mental influence on someone at a distance, the fear of pregnant women with desires to produce on the skin of his son a skin lesion, and finally the fear of the Evil Eye ability of some individuals, have something in common: the ancient notion of magic "transitive imagination". Of this curious "belief", that a particularly strong fantasy would be able to act at a distance, changing the external reality, the book (Immagini attive. Breve storia dell'immaginazione transitiva Le Monnier, Florence 2003), reconstructs (briefly) the "history": the convergence of neo-Platonism and Arab medicine until the dispute over power of imagination of the eighteenth century, through Boehme's theosophy and paracelsian philosophy. This marginal ontology, in contrast with Christian-Platonic-Cartesian dualism, provides a privileged perspective on the conflict of paradigms that is the basis of the pre-modern epistemology4.Spiritual body: moving from German Idealism backwardsSchelling's theme of "spiritual corporeality" attests to the value of a theosophical tradition which was well known to him (the speculative Swabian Pietism), especially of the "mysticism of nature" of the prelate of Murrhardt, Friedrich Christoph Oetinger (1702–1782). (Spiritual) body is the "ultimate goal of the works of God": this Oetinger’s thesis, that bypasses the one-sidedness of materialism and idealism, is the focus of Schelling’s real-idealism as kind of Christian philosophy (from the "glorious body", through the alchemical search of the "philosopher's stone" until the natural and aesthetic symbolism and nineteenth-century spiritualism). Oetinger and Schelling seek to overturn every spiritualistic spectrality (old, i.e. gnosis and docetism, and modern, i.e. Descartes). This book (Oetinger e Schelling). Teosofia e realismo biblico alle origini dell'idealismo tedesco, Segrate-Milan 2000, wants to check the influence of Oetinger on the development of Schelling's thought .The concept of the spiritual body (Il corpo spirituale. Ontologie “sottili” da Paolo di Tarso a Friedrich Christoph Oetinger, Mimesis, Milan 2006) has been a real regulative ideal of many pre-modern knowledge (not just esoteric) and of every “subtle” ontology: from eschatological Christian's resurrected body, through various metaphysics of intemediate bodies (the Neoplatonic ochema, the body of the Eucharist and Mary, the astral body of Paracelsus, the "spirit" of the medical philosophy, the physical and mystical imponderable matters, the alchemical quintessence, etc.) until the organic conception of Geistleiblichkeit of Christoph Friedrich Oetinger’s pansophia. The result is an ilic pluralism, a stratified ontology full of epistemological and soteriological expectations: an authentic revenant of Western thought that in the spiritual body has sought the condition of possibility not only of psychosomatic interaction but also of salvation (even pre-eschatological) of all things.5.Aesthetics and phenomenology of atmospheresHis current research includes phenomenology of body and perception and aesthetics of atmospheres (Atmosferologia. estetica degli spazi emozionali, Laterza, Rome-Bari 2010), a category that could be fruitful to design and account for those unintentional processes of human experience that some philosophers, psychopathists and (neo)phenomenologists like Hubertus Tellenbach, Hermann Schmitz, Gernot Böhme, Michael Hauskeller, Juergen Hasse (among others) name “atmospheric perceptions”. The expression “atmosphere”, usually meant to indicate something indeterminate, is for Griffero part of a situation in which meaning is dissolved in chaotic manifoldness, and sensing an atmosphere is a function of the lived body (Leib) as opposed to phenomena that are mediated by the senses. The atmospheric perception allows us to transcend the boundaries of the context we inhabit, in other words to bring together (bodily and affective) universalism and (cultural-idosyncratic) pluralism. In fact, in some contexts (philosophical, aesthetics, political, architectonic, pedagogical and so on) it seems that many things if not everything depend on the atmosphere in which something occurs: we talk for example about atmosphere of mutual understanding, of shared and well known insecurity, of fear and intimidation, and so on. Thus, with atmosphere we mean a special place that is occupied by an emotional (lived) space, by (in Heidegger’s terms) the state (Befindlichkeit) or mood (Stimmung) connected with it. The experiential or experienced space, that is not the same thing as the physical, objectively understood space as a place where we are located as physical bodies, is a horizon (an aura) that only arises when we enter it in a bodily form, because the body is a point where the spatial perspective as well as its atmosphere open up. As embodied beings, we are affected by the atmosphere created by the things around us, by a self-unfolding (ekstasis) of things, persons and places. Whereas Heidegger’s moods always presuppose a subjective response, we see atmospheres (in this provocative, anti-subjective sense) not as internal feelings of an individual or metaphors but as pre-subjective feelings, as spatially extended emotions. Therefore we do not create a space and its atmosphere in our own minds, as it emerges inevitably in connection with a situation, in our bodily connection with the world, above all with other people, as a phenomenon between people. So we can say that we are affected also by the atmospheric effect of something: it radiates an atmosphere and suggests to us a (this) judgement, and what’s important is that this atmosphere can be described adequately not only in the first person, i.e. is not present solely for the person who feels it only as long as he is aware of it. We must assume that intersubjectivity is grounded not only in (epistemic) objectivity, but in the quasi-objectivity of atmospheres as quasi-things: a quasi-objectivity that is demonstrated by the fact that we can communicate about atmospheres in language and that they can be experienced as surprising, and, on occasions, in contrast to one’s own mood: an example is when, in a cheerful mood, I enter a community in mourning and its atmosphere can transform my mood to the point of tears. Working out the situational and atmospheric nature of significances, we could put aside the problematic dichotomy subjectivism/objectivism and single out the atmospheres as proper object of our first-impression-life, as comparative mind-independent emotional qualities that confront us with a synaesthetical "affordance". So this quasi-objectivity of atmosphere gives proof of our existential and oecological passivity, namely of the fact that we are not (emotionally too) "master in our own house", providing a valuable perspective from which to reconsider the necessary attunement to the circumambient atmospheric meaning (or rather significance) of valid examples and ideas.6.Quasi-things What are quasi-things? First of all atmospheres, that is, feelings poured out into space and that we usually cannot change, but also pain, whose aggressiveness is at the same time a guarantee of identity of the subject. And then shame, both personal and vicarious (the one we feel for those who "should" be ashamed!); the felt-body, whose "isles" exceed the organs of the physical body; the look, so aggressive, in everyday life as in a portrait, that it produces a hemorrhage of our identity; and finally the twilight in its evocative vagueness.We all describe quasi-things, locate them into a space, recognize their intersubjective and amodal identity and, above all, affectively perceive their intrusiveness. Although ephemeral, intermittent, and without a cause outside of themselves, quasi-things, in fact, establish a specific communication with the felt-body of the perceiver, creating the emotional space in which he is located and that affects him in many ways . A philosophy that wishes to be not an abstract exercise, but a reflection on how we feel here and now, must then recognize that quasi-things and the affective qualities they generate are to be necessarily included in any ontological repertory worthy of that name.".
- Tonino_Griffero thumbnail Tonino_Griffero_b-w.JPG?width=300.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink index.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink index).
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink web.scuolaiad.it.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink cem.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink 20094.pdf.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink www.armando.it.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink cuem.html.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink www.francoangeli.it.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink www.gnam.beniculturali.it.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink www.guerini.it.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink www.humboldt-foundation.de.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink griffero.htm.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink www.laterza.it.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink www.marinotti.com.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink www.mimesisedizioni.it.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink cat_sensibilia.html.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink www.mondadorieducation.it.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink www.rosenbergesellier.it.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink www.sensibilia.it.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink index.html.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink La%20coperta%20troppo%20corta%20di%20Ingarden.html.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageExternalLink default.aspx.
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageID "33440319".
- Tonino_Griffero wikiPageRevisionID "602245557".
- Tonino_Griffero advert "February 2012".
- Tonino_Griffero hasPhotoCollection Tonino_Griffero.
- Tonino_Griffero name "Griffero, Tonino".
- Tonino_Griffero notability "October 2011".
- Tonino_Griffero orphan "December 2011".
- Tonino_Griffero shortDescription "Italian philosopher".
- Tonino_Griffero description "Italian philosopher".
- Tonino_Griffero description "Italian philosopher".
- Tonino_Griffero subject Category:Hermeneutists.
- Tonino_Griffero subject Category:Italian_philosophers.
- Tonino_Griffero subject Category:Living_people.
- Tonino_Griffero type CausalAgent100007347.
- Tonino_Griffero type Intellectual109621545.
- Tonino_Griffero type ItalianPhilosophers.
- Tonino_Griffero type LivingPeople.
- Tonino_Griffero type LivingThing100004258.
- Tonino_Griffero type Object100002684.
- Tonino_Griffero type Organism100004475.
- Tonino_Griffero type Person100007846.
- Tonino_Griffero type Philosopher110423589.
- Tonino_Griffero type PhysicalEntity100001930.
- Tonino_Griffero type Scholar110557854.
- Tonino_Griffero type Whole100003553.
- Tonino_Griffero type YagoLegalActor.
- Tonino_Griffero type YagoLegalActorGeo.
- Tonino_Griffero type Agent.
- Tonino_Griffero type Person.
- Tonino_Griffero type Person.
- Tonino_Griffero type Q215627.
- Tonino_Griffero type Q5.
- Tonino_Griffero type Agent.
- Tonino_Griffero type NaturalPerson.
- Tonino_Griffero type Thing.
- Tonino_Griffero type Person.
- Tonino_Griffero comment "Tonino Griffero (Asti, 1958) is an Italian philosopher and currently Professor of Aesthetics at the University of Rome Tor Vergata. He studied at the University of Turin (where he graduated in Philosophy under Gianni Vattimo's guidance in 1982) with a work on E. D. Hirsch's hermeneutics. Later he received his Ph.D from the University of Bologna (1992) and conducted post-doctoral research in Heidelberg as Humboldt-Fellow (1998–1999).".
- Tonino_Griffero label "Tonino Griffero".
- Tonino_Griffero label "Tonino Griffero".
- Tonino_Griffero sameAs Tonino_Griffero.
- Tonino_Griffero sameAs m.0h973gc.
- Tonino_Griffero sameAs Q7821500.
- Tonino_Griffero sameAs Q7821500.
- Tonino_Griffero sameAs Tonino_Griffero.
- Tonino_Griffero wasDerivedFrom Tonino_Griffero?oldid=602245557.
- Tonino_Griffero depiction Tonino_Griffero_b-w.JPG.
- Tonino_Griffero givenName "Tonino".
- Tonino_Griffero isPrimaryTopicOf Tonino_Griffero.
- Tonino_Griffero name "Griffero, Tonino".
- Tonino_Griffero name "Tonino Griffero".
- Tonino_Griffero surname "Griffero".